Beyond Denial and Abstinence: How Climate Change Can Bring Us A Better World

Colin Drumm’s “Beyond Denial and Abstinence” argues that we should define economic growth in terms of meeting human needs, as opposed to the prevailing definition centered on ruling-class interests. This argument is important when responses to climate change tend to center around issues of economic growth as either positive—as something that needs to be decoupled from carbon emissions—or inherently negative—as something that needs to be reversed. While we, the Cosmonaut Editorial Board, would argue for a more drastic economic change than the policies proposed at the end of this article, we believe that its general arguments are an important jumping-off point for a debate about how we understand economic growth in the context of climate change.

I am often, as I suspect so many of us are, paralyzed by an overwhelming sense of impending loss. The enormity of climate change and what it means for us and all that we hold dear induces in me physical anxiety that sometimes makes it almost impossible to think. The philosopher Thomas Hobbes once wrote that thought, or at least most thought, was guided by a passionate intention: our thinking, he said, is put into order by a desire. There is a desire, this desire is in the future, and it is in the service of this desire that we do our thinking. We think that we can get what we want. A simplistic model, no doubt. But I cannot help but notice that it offers, in its way, a diagnosis of my predicament: it has become impossible to think because it has become impossible to imagine a future that has any room for my desire in it, a future which “holds space” for my desire and thus makes it possible, in Hobbes’ terms, to think my way towards it. When I think of the future it has become impossible to think of anything but loss. I do not think I am the only one.

Conceived of in this way, it becomes possible to think of the problem of climate change as the problem of what another philosopher, Baruch Spinoza, would have called the problem of “sad affect.” An affect, for Spinoza, is not only a “feeling” or an “emotion” but also a relation to another entity: a sad affect is caused in me because I am interacting with another entity in such a way that my power, or my ability to produce and reproduce the conditions of my own existence, is reduced. We feel sad, that is, because there is something out there influencing us and making us less powerful, which means that we are less able to continue to be and to flourish. This makes us anxious. Climate change is a sad affect in precisely these terms: it is something “out there” which we relate to in such a way that it freezes our thinking and makes it less and less possible for us to react constructively to what is already happening all around us. This is a very dangerous situation. We are all, even those of us who claim to “believe” in climate change, a bit like a deer caught in the headlights of the future, and we must find a way to break ourselves out of this spell.

The issue, I think, is that we are in the habit of thinking of climate change as punishment for our sinful desires, and are thus caught in a trap “between denial and abstinence” in the way we approach the problem. On the one hand, denial: if climate change is real, and it is caused by our sinful desire, then that means I will be asked to give up my desire – not to drive and not to eat meat and so on – and I ward this off by pretending that climate change does not exist, or that it is not as bad as all that. I become a climate change denier in order to protect my desire. And on the other hand, there is abstinence: if climate change is real, and it is caused by our sinful desires, then I must renounce my desire by abstaining from consumption of various kinds in the hopes that this repentance might lead us to be forgiven and thereby saved. If we can just renounce enough of our desire, then climate change doesn’t have to happen: I give up on my desire in order to become a climate change abstainer. The problem is that no matter which side we take – denial or abstinence – climate change makes the future of desire impossible: either we give up what we want in order to save the world, or the world ends, in which case we can’t get what we want either. And when desire becomes impossible, we are overwhelmed by sadness and we cannot think.

Can we, then, refigure the problem of climate change in our political imagination such that we can escape from the trap of overwhelming and paralyzing sad affects? To do so would be to conceive of climate change in the mode of gain, rather than that of loss, to think of what it can enable us to desire rather than what it forbids us from desiring or shames us for desiring. How can our fight against climate change be guided by the passionate intention for a new and better world, rather than by sadness for a dying one?

To answer this question, we need to understand more precisely what is meant above by a “sinful desire.” We can give it a name: “economic growth.” The problem of climate change has generally been framed as a problem about the relationship between, on the one hand, the total carbon budget of the planet, and, on the other, the rate of growth of the economy. What capitalism desires is economic growth, and this desire is sinful: it is sinful because it seems to produce structural immiseration of some portion of its population alongside structural affluence of some others (the more traditional “paradox of poverty” in political economy), and it is also sinful because it burns carbon and thus threatens the continued availability of ecosystem services on which our lives depend. Debate about climate change, therefore, is generally structured by the question of the relation between the sinful desire, economic growth, and the consequences of that sin: climate change. This debate can, therefore, be understood in theological terms. Conservatives, for example, have tended to deny the existence of sin in the first place: economic growth is desire, sure, but there’s nothing sinful about it, because the poor deserve what they get and climate change isn’t real. They further argue that any attempt to fight climate change must necessarily harm economic growth, and that we therefore shouldn’t do it. 

Mainstream liberals, on the other hand, have tended to argue that growth and carbon can be reconciled: that we can achieve a state of what is called “absolute decoupling” in which a growing economy is combined with carbon emissions falling in absolute terms. The first strategy for achieving this reconciliation is what we might call a logic of indulgence, exemplified by the sale of “carbon credits:” an indulgence in a sinful desire (flying on an airplane, for example) can be “offset” by paying money to a philanthropic organization which, supposedly at least, uses it to sequester carbon elsewhere. The second strategy revolves around a technological optimism: the idea that economic growth produces technological progress, so that if we grow the economy, technology will improve, and improved technology will allow us to solve the carbon problem. 

Those to the left of the mainstream liberals – call them ecosocialists – have rightly tended to be suspicious at this optimistic framing of things. They point out that the sale of carbon indulgences and schemes like carbon cap-and-trade may exacerbate, rather than ameliorate, the social justice implications of climate change, and they view the liberals’ narrative of technological optimism with justified suspicion: such rhetoric is just as likely to be a veil over cynical profit-seeking as it is to be in the service of a genuine attempt to confront the problem. The ecosocialists thus agree with the conservatives that it is impossible to fight climate change without ending economic growth, but simply take the opposite conclusion: that we must “degrow” the economy in order to save the planet. 

What I have done above is to describe the problem of climate change as a version of what theology would call “theodicy” or the problem of evil. Simply put, the problem is that if God is omnipotent and benevolent, then why is there suffering in the world? Why wouldn’t God just make the world such that nothing evil existed in the first place? If economic growth has become a kind of “God” of our world, a God which grants us each day our daily bread and which we must serve if we are to retain his good pleasure, then the problem is why “sin” (that is, poverty and ecological collapse) still exist in the world. The conservative response is a kind of “low church” or protestant response: it says, the sacrifice of Christ means that we are in a state of grace, we have already been forgiven for our sins, so there is nothing to apologize for, and everything that happens is part of God’s plan, anyway. The mainstream liberal response is, by contrast, a “high church” or perhaps a Catholic response: it says, yes, we are always in danger of stepping into sin as a result of our desire, at every moment, but this does not mean you have to give up your desire – all you have to do is make a sacrifice, in the form of a monetary indulgence, to a churchly bureaucracy which will fix things by “balancing the books.” The ecosocialist response, finally, is a gnostic one: it says, in fact, the God of economic growth who made this world of capitalism is not a true God but a false, evil one, not God at all but a mere demiourgos, and the only way out of a world which has been irredeemably corrupted by its worship is to renounce this false God entirely. If economic growth is “what we want,” then we have no other choice but asceticism: the voluntary renunciation of desire aimed at a total escape from a world in which, as it is sometimes put, “no ethical consumption is possible.” 

In framing the problem in this way, I do not want to take up sides for one theodicy or another. Rather, my goal is to see if it is possible, once we understand the problem as being the problem of theodicy, to step outside of it entirely and think about things in a radically different way. How can we think of a way to approach the climate change problem that would be neither denial, nor indulgence, nor abstinence? If we could, we might be able to put desire back into the future, so to speak, and escape from the trap of “sad affect” in which we cannot think because we have lost the capacity to find a place for our desire in a future we can believe in. If we could, we might regain the ability to face the future with a renewed sense of purpose and yes, perhaps, even a feeling of joy. And this would make us immeasurably more powerful. So. How to begin?

I want to propose, in the remainder of this essay, that the problem can best be attacked not by attempting to resolve the contradiction between carbon and growth but by contesting the social construction of the category of “growth” in the first place. That is, while the amount of carbon in the atmosphere is simply an objective fact that can be measured more or less precisely, what we call “economic growth” is not an objectively real category. It is, essentially, an arbitrary accounting framework that can be, and has been, constructed in radically different ways over the relatively brief history of this concept’s existence. The Good News that I have come to offer is that there is, objectively speaking, no such thing as “economic growth,” and that because it doesn’t exist, we don’t need to worry too much about whether or not we have to give it up or whether it can be redeemed. In other words: “we got ninety-nine problems but economic growth ain’t one.” Let me elaborate upon and defend this assertion, and then conclude by offering an alternative. 

As Brett Christophers has argued, there is nothing “natural” or “inevitable” about the way in which the national income accounts (GDP) construct the category of “economic growth.”1 Following his argument, I suggest that the “fake objectivity” of GDP statistics can be understood as being the consequence of three “ideological slippages” in which normative claims are falsely represented as objective ones. Our quantitative and descriptive claims about the growth of the economy depend in an irreducible way, it turns out, upon prior normative or moral assumptions about how the world should be. I will focus on three “slipping points” at which normative or ideological claims are presented as objective or scientific ones, and thus produce the illusion of economic growth as a natural category: 1) the slippage between growth as the production of goods and services vs. growth as a return on investment, 2) the “banking problem,” or the question of the difference if any between “real” and “fictitious” capital and how to represent banks in national accounting terms, and 3) the problem of inflation and “hedonic value.” The upshot of this argument, to which I will return in closing, is that the “degrowth” analysis of the climate change problem is founded upon a mistaken premise: that the situation we are currently faced with is one of compounding economic growth combined with an accelerating carbon burn. Instead, I will argue, most if not all of the apparent “economic growth” in the United States for a number of decades is simply an illusion produced by a completely arbitrary and highly misleading accounting system. Measured in a more honest way, we are already, and have been, in a situation of declining economic growth in real terms. We are, therefore, in fact faced with the rather different scenario of an accelerating carbon burn accompanied not by economic growth but rather by an economy which is stagnant and declining and which has, indeed, been this way for some time. This change in the underlying assumptions that frame the problem has, as I hope to demonstrate, important consequences for the question of “what is to be done.”

First slippage. According to what might be called the “liberal constitution” — in the older sense of the word, not as a written document setting down fundamental rules, but rather a sort of governing sensibility that animates a political order — GDP is the central proxy measure for the “success,” and therefore the legitimacy of, a government. GDP is assumed to be “what everyone wants,” to be a universal consensus good, and thus functions as what Jean-Jacques Rousseau would have called the “General Will” – an object of desire which is good for everyone and to which, therefore, individual interests should be made to bend. It becomes the job of the government, therefore, to serve GDP: the government is seen to be a kind of fiduciary steward of “the economy,” the growth of which is supposed to be what is good for everyone without being bad for anybody and which can therefore be seen as a proxy for the interests of the people as such. 

But there are some obvious problems with conceiving of the maximization of GDP as the ethical foundation of state legitimacy. For one thing, there is the question of growth of what and for whom? We only have to open our eyes to the world around us to see that there are many people who do not seem to be benefitting from “economic growth,” and who are in fact being actively harmed for it: people who are pushed into homelessness as a result of gentrification and rising rents, for example. We might begin to suspect that “economic growth” really has much less to do with the question of whether the economy is serving the people who depend on it and much more to do with the question of whether investors will receive a good return on their investments. We might suspect that “economic growth” is really more about whether rich people get richer than whether all people in general experience a qualitative increase in the value of goods and services available to them. The fact that mainstream media commentators often use the phrase “economic growth” when what they are really talking about is the value of equities on the stock market is a symptom of this ideological misdirection. But we will need more than a suspicion. We need an analysis.

This brings us to the second slippage: the banking problem. Simply put, this is the “problem” that when banks are represented in the same way as other sectors of the economy in the national income accounts, what they show is a negative contribution to the total product of the economy. This is because the net interest payments accruing to the financial sector – the difference between what banks pay to borrow money and what they charge to lend it – seems to be simply a transfer of money out of the “productive” economy where it might have been invested in producing goods and services. When banks are treated in the most straightforward way in the accounts, they show up as being nothing more than a “drain” on the real economy, and in fact this is how they were usually treated in accounting prior to the post-War period, in accordance with the distinction that was made in classical political economy, from Smith to Marx, between “value” and “rent.” According to this way of thinking, the “real” economy produces value, while the “fictitious” economy doesn’t produce anything but only extracts rents from other sectors that do.

Since the introduction of the first international accounting framework by the United Nations in 1953, GDP measures have attempted to “solve” the banking problem in various ways so that the financial sector could be represented as making a productive contribution to the national product. The SNA 1953 framework represented the net interest payments to banks as an “intermediate product” supplied to other sectors of the economy as inputs: producing a refrigerator could, in other words, be said to “consume” bank credit in the same way that it consumes aluminum, and the banking sector’s contribution to total product could be represented as such. This method was politically controversial, however, as it increased the imputed product of the banking sector at the expense of other sectors, and it also had the curious implication that the product of a sector would vary according to its capital structure, or whether it was funded by debt or equity. An alternative framework, the SNA 1968, was introduced that solved this problem by taking an even further step into absurdity, inventing a wholly fictitious notional sector of the economy that could be said to “consume” the product of the financial sector without thereby detracting from any of the others.

These two frameworks were superseded in 1993 by a new System of National Accounts which, finally, succeeded in defining finance as unambiguously productive. It did so by disaggregating the lending and borrowing activities of banks, and treating each of them separately as a productive function in their own right. Rather than seeing banks as collecting a spread between their cost of funds and returns and lending, that is, this new framework conceived of them as making a profit on both sides by introducing the concept of the “reference rate” or the “pure cost of borrowing funds.”2 Banks were understood to make a profit, and thus a contribution to national product, on the borrowing side by borrowing at a rate below the “pure cost” of borrowing funds, and on the lending side by lending money at a rate above it. Since interest rate spreads are understood in financial theory as being compensation for risk, this framework answers the question of what banks “produce” by representing them as being paid for the service of assuming financial risk by moving it off the balance sheets of their counterparties and onto their own. The experience of 2008 shows, however, that we have good reason to doubt this justification since the doctrine of “too big to fail” asserts that the state is under an implicit obligation to assume the systemic risks of the banking sector. If the state pays to bail the banking sector out when its risks go bad and then offloads this payment to the population through austerity, how can it still be possible to say that banks provide a service to the economy by assuming its risk?

There are more details to this history, which are quite interesting in their own right, but our present purposes will be served by this brief summary. The point I want to make here is simply that the notion of “GDP” is only about 65 years old, and during this history it has undergone some fairly drastic changes revolving around the question of whether banks should be understood as a productive sector of the economy and how to represent them as such if they are. It is only by doing this, crucially, that we can show “growth” in the figures at all: if we accounted for the financial sector in the way it was done in the early 20th century, by treating banks just like any other sector of the economy, then our figures would say that the economy has not grown, or has not grown very much, or has perhaps even been shrinking, for something like the last 40 years. While some critics from the left, the economist Michael Hudson for example, have advocated reviving the value/rent distinction from classical political economy and thus redefining finance as inherently unproductive, we do not even need to accept the rather dubious and moralizing claim that financial activities are essentially and inevitably “sterile” to doubt the legitimacy of counting, by definition, all profits accruing to the financial sector as a real contribution to the total productive output of the economy. Certainly, it seems intuitively plausible that financial activities might, at least in some cases, represent a pure parasitic burden on the economy and thus not a contribution to a product at all but simply a form of rent or extraction.

Thus, showing growth at all in the national accounts requires that we make certain assumptions rather than others about the productivity of finance. But this is only speaking in nominal terms: about the difficulties involved in measuring the size of the economy in present dollars. This brings us to the third and final slippage: the problem of inflation. We are accustomed to being presented graphs of various economic phenomena measured in graphs of dollars “adjusted for inflation,” with the implication that this is a trivial or at least completely technical operation which must be carried out in the background before we begin to think about what we are looking at. But there are, in fact, deep conceptual and even political difficulties involved in the construction of a “deflator,” or an index of the value of money over time which allows the “nominal” prices which actually physically exist in the world to be normalized to an ideal standard of “real” prices which remain commensurable with themselves over time. The first and most obvious problem is that the construction of the deflator requires the construction of a consumption basket: we need to imagine an ideal person who consumes a certain basket of goods and then measure the change of price of this basket over time. Since we are concerned to ask about the relationship between economic growth and carbon emissions, we need, in order to compare their relationship quantitatively, to construct a deflator for the period of about a century-spanning from the emergence of the petroleum economy in the early 20th century to the present day. 

As Robert J. Gordon has illustrated quite forcefully in The Rise and Fall of American Growth, the construction of such a “hundred-year deflator” is faced with the dizzying task of organizing the sweeping and revolutionary changes in technology and standard of living that took place during this period. In order to construct the hundred-year deflator, we need to actually produce a couple of dozen different consumption baskets, a new one for each time a major new innovation is produced or when new products replace old ones and then stitch them together to produce the illusion of a continuous series. We have to ask, that is, not only what happens to the value of money as goods get cheaper or more expensive, but what happens to the value of money as it becomes able to purchase qualitatively new goods or goods which have improved in quality. The construction of the deflator thus requires a qualitative — and therefore normative and value-laden — assessment of not only what counts as “a good” but also how good it is. The most notorious and commonly cited example of this problem is the television: as the number of pixels in the television increases, the “hedonic value” of the television rises, which means that the value of the dollar in the inflation measure rises with it. When someone reports to you what the rate of inflation is, therefore, they are also implicitly ordering you to care about televisions and their number of pixels and to accept that they matter for determining the value of money. Now, I don’t know about you, but there are few things in the world that I care about less than televisions and their pixels, so this kind of thing makes me a little suspicious.

I’ll return to this problem of hedonic value adjustment in a moment, but first I want to strengthen the point by giving an example that cannot possibly be dismissed as a quibble. It is bad enough that it may be somewhat difficult to decide which goods count and how good they are, but there is, even more troublingly, an ambiguity about whether some “goods” might not, in fact, be “bads.” It is, in other words, not only a question of magnitude but also of sign which must be decided by the normative accounting process by which a deflator is constructed. Let me begin with a more obvious example before proceeding to some subtler ones. A point around which the above discussion of the banking problem hinged was the relation between the financial sector and non-financial firms: should the money flowing out of the non-financial sector towards the financial sector be understood as a transfer payment or instead as representing the provision of an intermediate good, just like coal or steel? What we did not consider, at that point, was the question of how to understand income accruing to the financial sector from households directly: are these payments to be considered a transfer payment (i.e. a rent) or as a final good, or something which households consume and enjoy and benefit from? Because, in the standard accounting, finance is defined as productive, it is treated as the latter: everything that the household sector pays to the banking sector is, by definition, a payment for goods rendered. To define things in this way is to deny outright and on a priori grounds the mere possibility of “predatory finance,” or credit which does not improve the ability to debtor to repay it and is thus very difficult to ever escape. Might it not be more reasonable to see at least some forms of consumer finance as more of a way to extract money from people who don’t have any, than as the provision of any real good or “service”? The ever-escalating cost of the insurance needed to pay arbitrarily inflated costs of medical care in the United States is only one obvious example of a situation in which we should be leery of assuming that all forms of consumer finance are actually “goods.”

We do not, however, need to appeal to the especially problematic financial sector in order to find cases in which “goods” might be better understood as “bads.” The automobile is one example. Now, there’s no question that a lot of people like cars, find them exciting and aesthetically pleasurable, enjoy being able to go places in them, and so on. From this perspective, the automobile is a good: you pay money for it, you get the good, that’s growth! But this perspective can be turned on its head if we consider the idea that owning an automobile is now, at least for many people, a requirement for participation in society in a way that was not the case for people who lived in the past because they inhabited built environments which did not take the ownership of cars for granted. Is being forced to buy and fuel and service an automobile so that you can sit in traffic while commuting to a job across low-rise sprawl something that you get to do with your money, or is it something that you have to do with your money? If it’s the latter, the automobile might start to seem more like a tax than a good, a suspicion which is hardly allayed by the fact that many cities intentionally dismantled their public transportation infrastructures at the behest of automobile manufacturers in the early 20th century. Or suppose, in another example, that a new kind of laundry detergent is produced which costs half as much as the old kind. Since this makes the value of the dollar go up, it will show up as growth in the inflation-adjusted national income accounts. Now suppose, also, that this new detergent, unbeknownst to anyone, happens to give you cancer. The medical care you receive to treat this cancer will also be treated in the accounts as growth, since it’s a service that you pay for and thus counts as a good! In this case we have not only what mainstream economics calls a “negative externality,” or a cost which is not accounted for in the price of a good, but a negative externality which is actually counted as a good in another section of the accounts. We thus have a system of accounting in which the production of sickness is counted as a good and in which the improvement of the overall level of health of the population, such that it consumed less healthcare, would be counted as an economic disaster. While this situation may indeed be “growth” in the sense of providing elites with the opportunity to accumulate assets, it cannot, with any honesty at all, be counted as an increase in the amount of real goods and services produced by the economy.

All of this is, I hope, enough to demonstrate the point that all possible measures of “economic growth” are not natural categories but rather normative, value-laden, and politically contingent constructions, which are, most fundamentally, designed to provide a theoretical legitimation of the status quo rather than to faithfully represent anything that is actually going on in the world.  I will, therefore, leave my critique here, and turn to a more important question: what is to be done? The climate crisis makes it unavoidably obvious that the maximization of GDP as it is constructed is no longer satisfactory grounds for the legitimacy of the state: what good is it that the state brings us a higher GDP if it doesn’t act in order to ensure our very survival? Very well — but then what? What should we do? My answer, in a slogan, is that any serious response to the crisis must be prepared to “seize the means of accounting” and impose new frameworks for measuring inflation and economic product which are aligned with, rather than opposed to, the necessity of protecting and cultivating essential biosphere services. That is, we can, if we gain control of the government institutions whose job it is to define and produce these statistics, simply order them to create a measure to replace GDP which goes up when we do things that save the planet, by construction. Since there is no particular reason that we have to measure growth and inflation in the way that we do, there is no particular reason that we cannot simply decide to measure them in a radically different way. To produce such a measure in all of its details would be well beyond the scope of this essay, so instead, I will close by putting sketching an outline of what I feel would be the most relevant considerations.

First, let’s return to the problem of “hedonic value adjustment” in the calculation of inflation statistics. According to the theory that governs the construction of these measures, an improvement in the quality of a good must be measured as deflation, or as an increase in the value of the dollar since you can now get a better microwave or a better car or a better computer for the same price. Some economists, of late, have even gone so far as to argue that inflation is overestimated because it fails to take into account how many apps our smartphones have on them, and thus how much-increased value we get out of owning them. Thus, the inflation statistics are very careful to try to capture and incorporate all of the “upside” of the fossil economy in the sense of representing the way in which modern people seem to be able to “enjoy” a number of qualitatively novel good that were unavailable in previous epochs. But these statistics do not incorporate the downsides of the fossil economy in the same way. For example, consider two houses which are otherwise identical, with all the same faucets and all the same windows. However, when you open the faucets in one house, clean water comes out, while the faucets in the other house produce only a reeking brown ooze. Open the windows in the first house, and clean air comes in, while doing the same in in the second house gives rise to wafts of acrid, toxic smoke. Surely, for any reasonable person, this would qualify as a severe hedonic value impairment: but inflation statistics make no mention of such phenomena.  Rather, to the extent that it spurs the sale of bottled water and air masks, such a situation would only be counted as yet more growth. Another example is that of produce: while monoculture and factory farming have produced a secular decline in the levels of nutrition in our food, and thus our health. While it would be reasonable to suppose that a tomato with less vitamins in it, or a tomato which has been bred for color at the expense of flavor, should be “hedonically adjusted” downwards in value, this sort of consideration plays no role in the accounting. But it could. If we took into account the negative hedonic value adjustments that accompany industrial monocultures and the fossil economy in assessing the changing “real” value of the consumption basket, we would produce much higher estimates of inflation and thus much lower estimations of inflation-adjusted growth.

Second, the banking problem and the question of inequality. The modern method of accounting assumes, purely by definition and by means of extremely creative accounting, that all financial activities must be productive and all revenues accruing to the banking sector must be payments for some good which the banking sector has provided. Now, our problem here is the truth almost surely lies somewhere between the classical view that banking is sterile and the modern view that all banking is necessarily productive. While it seems obvious to me that much financial activity, especially in our own time, is more or less purely parasitic, it also doesn’t seem quite right to deny flat-out that the financial sector “does something useful.” Indeed, the attempt to distinguish between productive credit and predatory credit is an old problem, perhaps even one of the oldest problems in legal history: while it was generally agreed that there was or should be a difference, lawyers and theologians have labored for millennia attempting to put their finger on exactly what that difference was. I therefore disagree with Hudson and others who call for a revival of the distinction in classical political economy between value and rent, on the grounds that the legal questions involved are simply too thorny. 

Instead, I propose to sidestep the problem by recognizing that what is really at issue is not the inherent morality of any particular financial contract but rather the role that the financial sector has in driving wealth inequality. Wealth inequality is not only, as I believe and as you should too, a bad thing in itself, but a driver of climate change due to the fact that the propensity to burn carbon has been shown to vary linearly with income — as opposed to life satisfaction, for which additional income has marginal returns. 100 dollars means much more to a poor person than to a rich person, in terms of how much it improves their life, but the amount of carbon they end up emitting as a result will be about the same.

The real problem with the financial sector, then, is that it redistributes money away from the poor and towards the rich, who use it to squander more and more carbon in an increasingly vain effort to become slightly more happy (riding helicopters to the tops of mountains to take selfies, e.g.). Rather than attack the financial sector directly by wading headlong into the quagmire of attempting to legislate the difference between a speculation and a hedge, therefore, I propose that we simply attack wealth inequality directly by normalizing GDP over the Gini coefficient. This would have the effect of counting growth at the bottom as “more” than growth at the top, with the effect that progressive redistribution would “count” as growth in itself. While this aspect of the proposed accounting framework would not contribute to reducing the total amount of carbon emitted directly, it would help ensure that the carbon we do emit is used more efficiently to promote the well being and life satisfaction of the mass of the population rather than of an elite few. It would, that is, improve the ratio of “happiness per ton,” as well as helping to ameliorate, as a good in its own right, the deleterious and disruptive effects of rampant inequality on society.

Third: inflation statistics should be “adjusted for climate change” not only through the negative hedonic value adjustment of existing goods, but by the introduction of a fictitious accounting entry representing a basket of non market biosphere services into the consumption basket. (If the economics protest at this, we will remind them that the SNA 1968 introduced a wholly fictitious sector into the economy in order to justify the productivity of finance, and that that they are not the only ones who can play at such games). This can be accomplished simply by having the government issue everyone a sum, say a thousand dollars, and then immediately taxing it back in the form of a mandatory fee to a public biosphere services utility. This would therefore be counted as an item in the consumption basket without impacting the consumer’s flow of funds in any way, and its value could then be pegged to an index of air quality, water quality, biodiversity, and so on. If the index declined, then this would show up as inflation, since the same fee was being paid for a worse service, and that would negatively impact the growth figures. If the index went up, however, this would count as deflation and thus a contribution to growth.

Fourth: long-term debt markets should be forced to account for the risk of climate-change driven disruption by the introduction of “mark-to-climate” accounting. As I write in August 2019, the major financial news is that the yield curve has inverted (meaning that investors, anomalously, have a preference for long term debt over short term) and that the yield on the 30 year Treasury bond has dropped below 2 percent, which would be a jaw droppingly low figure were it not much higher than current rates in peer economies around the world. Since financial theory takes yield or interest to be a payment for risk, this means that financial markets currently see the middle term future as much less risky than the immediate present, which is a curious implication at a time when forests are burning over the world from the Arctic to the Amazon. Surely the 30 year time horizon cannot be so un-risky as all of that, and it is therefore hard not to get the impression that the financial markets themselves are in a state of intense climate change denial. 

I  propose, therefore, that “mark-to-climate” accounting should to seek to force debt markets to reflect climate reality in two ways. The first is that since bond markets play, or at least seen to play, a disciplining function in the fiscal activity of the state, all bondholders should be paid a premium upon expiry which varies with the biosphere services index proposed above: the higher the index goes, the higher the premium, which might in addition become a haircut should the index fall below a certain threshold. This would incentivize bondholders to allow states to borrow cheaply in order to pursue projects that improve the index, and disincentivize them from punishing states for engaging in such activities. The second main prong of mark-to-climate accounting would be the construction of a “climate chaos” index which measured the volatility of a basket of indicators like temperature, rainfall, and so on, accompanied by the requirement that financial institutions purchase insurance against it.  This can be justified on the grounds that the doctrine of “too big to fail” offloads systemic financial risk onto the state as a liability, and because climate change increases the risk of systemic social and financial failures, financial institutions should have to pay more for this implicit insurance policy the more erratic the weather gets. These institutions would therefore be disincentivized from funding economic activity that fueled climate change and therefore raised their premiums, and incentivized to fund activity that stabilized the climate in an effort to reduce them. 

It is my hope that the foregoing is enough to show that such a project is not only possible, but eminently practical, and open to a great deal of flexibility: many more proposals along the lines of those above could be given. The most important point I wish to convey here is that the apparent contradiction between “growth” and an ecological future has nothing to do with anything inherent in any supposed “laws of economics.” This so-called problem of growth is not actually a problem at all, but an ultimatum, issued to us by those who would rather see the world burn than allow their power and wealth to be diminished. We must refuse to take this ultimatum at face value, as the liberals do when they seek to show how the fight against climate change can be reconciled with growth, or as the ecosocialists do when they argue that growth is an objective thing which is the source of our problems and which we must therefore oppose. It is, I think, a matter of basic strategy that the best response to an ultimatum is another ultimatum: the demand that we must not count what the economy gives us separately from the continued existence of a world in which we could enjoy it. In this way, perhaps, we can once again make the future a place where desire is possible.

Seize the means of accounting! We have a world to win, and nothing to lose but our despair.

Power as Savior and Destroyer of the World

Latest from Cold and Dark Stars. Economic laws are sold to us by those in power as natural laws beyond our own control rather than forms of class power that can be challenged and overcome.  

I

The whole conversation is rigged.

Now that climate change has turned up on the radar of economists and policymakers, they are pretending we had it too good, that we lived in a utopia of cheap consumer goods, long lifespans, automobiles, and gadgets, and that our own self-indulgence brought us the trouble.1 The economists and industry captains were selling us what we wanted since their product was good: economic growth and cheese sticks. They just didn’t know about the caveat: the perturbation of the earth into a new thermodynamic equilibrium, one that could have extreme consequences in our fragile human systems.

They say everyone shares the blame since we were too happy indulging in their products. That is how it’s sold to us: salvation is to be inconvenienced by not using that straw, that grocery bag, and walking to the corner store instead of driving.2 These meaningless inconveniences are merely psychological pressure points to suggest the greater unpleasantries of a radical solution. They are training us to imagine the greater sacrifice, which inevitably means austerity. Reversing some of this utopia is the panacea of the illness of civilization. If we have grown too fat the solution inevitably means austerity.  

They know this story is awful, that it is a hard sell. But it does a couple of things. First, it sells the decisions done by power brokers in the last two centuries or so as overall good, the unsustainability an unfortunate caveat. Whatever comes next must look like the present social order, because it is good. Having a tiny percentage of the world population controlling the resource distribution and the rest having to fight for certain “jobs”3 that decision-makers, asset holders, and professionals have decided are useful in order to warrant access to nourishment and shelter is seen as a good and realistic model. The second thing it does is quite magical.  Because this story is a hard sell, and normal people are not willing to sacrifice their lifestyle, the elite can pretend they are not pushing for change for the demos does not want it.4 The poor democratic souls!

Finally, the culmination of this story is an argument for human nature. They say humans are naturally greedy convenience seekers and have short attention spans.  According to the educated, cable tv consumers, and anxious mortgage and index fundholders, the majority won’t buy the story because human nature is diseased.5 There are two corollaries to this story: that the present social order is perfected for the human soul, and there is nothing to be done because any “better world” is incompatible with the human soul. 

This story is such a monstrous, self-serving con that it should infuriate any person that dares to use their brain.  

II

The above story can only begin to be questioned by reassembling many of the concepts we inherited from many smart, intellectual types. 

Perhaps this reassembling must start within me. Many of my past writings have been about solutions to the ills of something called capitalism. One identifies this discrete epoch of “capitalism” and then describes the force that will destroy it. This capitalism, a logic that permeates the world, manipulates all living things for the purpose of profit/capital growth. This includes the destruction of many beings and worlds for some venal abstraction. The way it goes is that there is no agency behind these structures, the economy, the market, or “capital” are autonomous machines with their own inner programming, the businessman, workers, and politicians merely its puppets. 

Usually the expositors of this story are proud that it counters ordinary common sense. Much of the uneducated instincts you can follow in youtube, or eavesdrop at the bar, blame the problems of the world on a group of people with inordinate influence, hence the prevalence of conspiracy theories. The instinctual story gives a large agency to the “puppet-masters” that are made of flesh and blood. The intellectual, such as a certain breed of Marxist, will say that deposing the flesh and blood  “puppet-masters” would not do much since the only puppet master is capital.6 How do you overthrow Capital, which is G-d?

This argument is structurally the same as the neoliberal argument. It claims that there is something called the Economy that follows certain laws of motion, and these laws of motion say that the Economy would become crippled the moment the State is used as a tool against the elite, for devaluation and capital strikes would appear.7 This “Economy”, which is based on reification of certain limited, mathematical models in textbooks, has become a favorite sword of the right-wing to defend congealed interests. 

I am not claiming the scenario exposed by the neoliberals and the Marxists that parallel them is unrealistic. Instead, I would argue that what they refer to as the “Economy” or “value” is merely a power relation, imposed by a class upon the other, in other words, a human relation. The economic problems we tend to talk about, such as capital flight and devaluation, are merely questions of power and therefore freedom. By reframing this dialectic in terms of power, freedom of is injected ontologically; the scaffolding is made of humans deliberating. 

One could counter my argument by saying that there is a certain impartiality of the economy.  Industry captains can’t merely price their commodities at any value they wish. Establishing more humane labor laws in their industries abroad, or socializing certain industries, would make the United States less competitive in the global market, which would deny the state important revenues that could be used to build schools or hospitals.8 Yes, in some futures, some very realistic ones, this could happen. But it’s not because of some objective “Economy” that favors certain rules over others. It’s merely a question of power.

Instead, powerful agents today are embedded in a network of power nodes, and they must compete and maneuver against other power brokers. This creates emergent tidal waves, that may sweep across the network of nodes, creating the notion of an impartial earthquake. But at the end of the day, this turbulence cannot just be categorically tamed with “laws”, and the ripples still are shaped by the hierarchy of sovereigns. This is the reason why some countries can run higher debt tallies than others, or why sometimes counterintuitive policies such as quantitative easing do not cause catastrophic inflation. And it is in this picture that one may find the answer to politics in this warming world.

Let’s come back to the “uneducated” instinct, the vector that points to conspiracy theories. The instinct is partly right but also flawed. It is a healthier instinct than the intellectualized, anthropomorphization of the “economy” and capital since it at least offers the possibility of freedom. But the flaw of this instinct is that there is no discrete entity called the elite that controls the world. 

Rather, it is a continuous distribution, a gradient across a fluid of power. This gradient radiates from the billionaires at the top but also includes the professionals that monopolize certain technocratic jobs, the white families that own assets and index funds (which usually are represented in the mainstream, think of the GOP and the DNC),  and the meritocratic elites that structure the job and educational pipelines so that certain people are destined to lord over others. But even these “little” bourgeoisies are an approximation, as class power isn’t a discrete stratification but a continuous gradient. This is the problem of the slogan “against the one percent”. A social system cannot be sustained by the support of only a tiny elite. And a political project that does not bring reckoning with the current power gradient will fail in changing the story. 

The solution then is to somehow nudge this class power vector into another direction, which is ultimately what Marx wanted. 

III

The question of power is very deep. Nietzche thought everything was power all the way down, the immanent substance of the Universe. Hobbes referred to value as power, and Adam Smith, the father of classical political economy, approvingly cited Hobbes’ quote. 

It’s a banal question as well. We identify that the state ultimately has the right to kill us, throw us into a cage, and force us to act in ways we don’t agree with. We remember the bully at school, the authoritarian father. Power has scarred all of us, and we secretly desire it.  Some of us play with these roles in the bedroom, perhaps trying to exorcize the immanence of power through the most primeval combination of sweat and blood. 

Power is interwoven with freedom. Power cannot be understood as merely inertial, the violence of blind laws.  This is not because power is an endeavor of humans only; in the same way Nietzche thought power was immanent to the Universe, so is freedom, and ultimately they are both the faces of the same Ultimate. Power is arbitrariness which is freedom. 

Let’s analyze how an ontology of power and freedom enriches the original story.  Global warming is often explained as a straightforward process of quasi-deterministic laws. In the last two centuries, humanity has experienced unprecedented economic growth, which economists have tied as being coupled with carbon emissions. The carbon dioxide in the atmosphere acts as a powerful greenhouse gas that traps the radiation from the sun, preventing the escape of heat into space. As the amount of atmospheric carbon dioxide increases, less radiation is released into space, increasing the temperature of the Earth. This increase in temperature will feed into dangerous feedback loops, such as the reduction of ice cover, or the enhancing of other powerful greenhouse gases such as water vapor and methane. 

The economists then argue that global warming would cause GDP losses. Extreme events such as floods and droughts would negatively affect agriculture, livestock,  infrastructure, and health. These damages, in turn, could cause teleconnections into other sectors such as finance.9  

However, this above account is impoverished in so far it occludes the role of humans deliberation, and therefore power. It does not reveal the malleability and contingency of the coupling of economic growth to carbon emissions, or our understanding of GDP. Furthermore, the entities of the Earth-system are considered inert, subject to deterministic laws. 

A better and richer account could be the following. The current sovereigns of the Earth thought they could control it to do their bidding, as if the earth system, with its water vapor, oceans, ice-sheets, and cyclones, was a submissive object that will lay bare to our manipulations. The power of these sovereigns is distributed but stratified, so there is not only one king, and the emergent processes of these networks of deliberations give rise to the apparent “impartiality” and the illusion of law-like behavior. This complex distribution of power is often referred to as the “economy” or the “market”, but this conceptualization often hides the element of deliberation and freedom of its actors, subsuming them under scientific regularities. The lack of absolute monopoly over the commodities from some of the players gives the appearance of laws that exist outside the deliberation of States, notwithstanding the violent and colonial monopolies  (e.g. East Indian Company, Hudson’s Bay Company, Dutch East India Company) that emerged from the birth pangs of the current world system. 

The market becomes an illusory category, a mystification of the fluid of nodes that embeds together power brokers like the state, the creatures and objects that form the Earth, and other sovereigns, human formations such as insurgent parties, activist groups, and clandestine paramilitaries, etc. Ultimately, this ensemble forms an immanent, turbulent fluid, full of vortexes, tidal waves, and shocks, horizontally wide but stratified.  One of the stratifications of this fluid is class power. Class power can be represented as a multidimensional vector along the stratification of this power-fluid. This vector not only encodes 19th-century factory bosses, or the top 0.1 percent but includes all sorts of asset holders such as mortgage holding, white families in select zip codes that concentrate the means of intergenerational wealth.

This power-fluid is alive with freedom. I stretch the term life here, for it does not only include what is referred as life by biologists, creatures with a chemically defined genetic code but also includes the turbulent ocean and atmosphere, the chemical and hydrological cycles that enshroud the Earth with clouds, the cyclones caused by the interaction of the earth’s spin with temperature gradients. Sure, some aspects of this system appear fairly predictable and therefore give the appearance of determinism and lifelessness. For example the orbit of the Earth, the trajectory of an individual electron,  the weather within one day, the job market within a month, the average lifespan of a dog. However, these systems are tractable until they aren’t, as many of them may become subject to shocks in the same way the behavior of a friend might be familiar until they fall into a deep depression. The emergence of determinism and stochasticity is often seen as noise, as an effect of not having enough information about the system. But this view is just a theology. Regardless of whether we find this noise as ontologically superfluous, the indeterminism still slaps us with full force. The Earth system is not behaving as it “should”, as the economy experiences shocks, love sometimes withers, and flying cars haven’t appeared but the internet has. A more interesting and useful ontology is acknowledging the freedom and agency of matter, not falling into the Christian trap of considering only humans free. 

The structural determinists, such as the economists and their laws, and the Marxists and their “value” are merely tweaking the Christian theology, for the old philosophers of Christendom considered matter dead while the human being was ensouled. These economists/Marxists merely take this incorrect ontology of dead matter and include the human being (and the world system) as made of billiard balls with positions and momentum vectors assigned to them. 

Against the “price distortion” and “law of value types” that think of themselves so clever because they wield vague regularities as absolute laws, power, the real immanent substance, is made of agents consciously deliberating, albeit lacking complete omnipotence, and surrounded by a fog of war. It is in the game of power where the class struggle becomes intelligible. 

IV

Class power could be summarized as the strategic capture of resources of one class (Colin Drumm) over the other. Class here is a demographic description, that only becomes intelligible in the sense that it is hierarchical: a class captures resources at the expense of others. Class power should not be thought of as a discrete distribution of a couple of classes. Instead, it is a continuous distribution. 

The most important theorist of class power was Karl Marx. His life’s project was to show that the economic and political stories were cons validating the most powerful class during his era: the bourgeoisie. The law, religion, ideology, and even some “science” were merely justifications of the bourgeoisie’s class power, narratives that made the strategic capture of resources of a tiny elite seem “natural”.

Those who are privileged reflect the cosmic, static order. The Chinese emperors came from Heaven, God gave the right to kings to rule, and today the elite rule because they reflect human nature. The elite embodies democratic nature to accumulate property and assets which inevitably leads to the optimal hierarchy. 

Here is where the con within the stories about global warming is revealed. The current narrative of climate change is sheer class power.  Yes, the elite must acknowledge the power of the earth system to destroy the civilization they rule. But at the same time, they must remind their subjects that right now they have the highest possible standard of living, and that nudging the system too much would destabilize this standard.

In fact, it is the projection of their power that makes us addicted to their world.  For it is not only chemical or sexual dependency that their products offer, such as processed sugar, or digital porn. More importantly, they sell us the illusion that through their products we can become like them, socially recognized by the rest. The search for social recognition is ancient. Amongst certain small, indigenous egalitarian societies, “big men” try to outdo each other with gifts and potlatches to become honored. In modernity this impulse is channeled into owning larger houses, better cars, having a degree from a good University. They rob the children from their childhood so that someday they can become accomplished professionals that can be paraded in the deranged pageantry of the technocratic castes. Meanwhile, we all end up playing, touching, and caring less, for we are conned into keeping up with the Joneses.

This is not human nature, it is the product of a certain group of people trying to maintain their privileges at all costs, and the historical directionality imposed by the phenotype of that modern elite (capitalists, bankers, professionals, asset holders). It doesn’t matter that some of them may suffer in the process – their kids may kill themselves because of the pressures of grad school, or professionals may develop mental illnesses by stuffing their skull with information concerning their assets, debts, and career moves. What matters is that they are not the worst off, that people below them are more miserable.  

This world that serves the elite was manufactured through deliberative actions, even if decision-makers could not be aware of all the outcomes. The stamp of the asset holders’ freedom scars every planetary entity. Therefore, It is only through the deliberative actions of the non-asset holding classes that this world can change. 

V

The structures of the world are not absolute and can be nudged into a direction through the imposition of power

There is no autonomous capital that is subject to its own internal desires. There are no “objective” economic laws that the neoliberals love to hark on about. The spurious regularities of innovation, stable currency, and debt are place holders for embedded power dynamics that are linked to imperialism and the quasi-monopolies of financial systems (American and English banks), technology (intellectual property law and corporate secrets), and monetary inertia triggered by the sheer violence of world wars (the death of the gold standard, the creation of the Breton-Woods regime). It is power all the way down.  When someone talks about “innovation”, “entrepreneurship”, GDP, and inflation, chances are that they are interpreting noise (e.g. random initial conditions that gave access to important resources and tools), or mislabelling the spurious regularities of the powerful (quasi-monopolies over the financial system like the US and the U.K own).

However, the freedom of the powerful opens our own possibility of freedom. There are no blind laws that oppose the stability of the earth system, the creation of a softer and brighter world of more play and touch. The streamlines in the power-fluid that carry the world into warming are imposed by certain, powerful entities. Yet we can impose our own cyclones, jet-streams, and eddies by building channels that change the course of the fluid. 

VI 

The change of conversation always implies the imposition of class power. And class power is not merely words, but institutions, resources, an army – in other words, the state.

Perhaps we can find an interesting example in the Russian Revolution, as Andreas Malm noted.10 In 1917, famine scourged Russia, probably due to a climate fluctuation. The tzarist regime was too incompetent and married to the interests of landlords to be able to use the machinery of the state to solve the food distribution problem. Instead, Lenin posed the question of the workers and peasants taking power, organized through a political party, to solve the food allocation problem, since the interests of the non-propertied classes aligned with the solution. There is a pedagogic parallel to our current predicament here. The Earth-system is becoming dangerously unstable, to the point where food price variability may nudge civilization towards collapse. The state’s scaffold is too married to asset wealthy classes to be able to enact the radical changes required for a flourishing society that responsibly stewards the Earth system. Only a Party that is not subject to these interests, that is, a Party of workers, farmers, the indigenous and racialized, could realistically steward the Earth system and therefore save civilization. 

If a Party of this type does not emerge, reactionary formations may occupy the vacuum left behind by environmental instability.  The far-right is excited about the incoming climate refugee crisis to help them gain support for a xenophobic ethnostate.

The question of power is intimately linked not only to the access to resources but also to how we ethically and spiritually interface with those resources. The response to climate change cannot merely be some imposed austerity in consumer goods while the power structures that interface humans between themselves and the Earth remains intact. The question of climate change can’t be resolved through the technocratic administration of resources while human relationships and the associated conceptual universe stays the same.

VII

Throughout the last century, the ruling classes have rewired our serotonin pathways to become addicted to what they offer: cheap porn, diplomas, credit, status, SUVs, and plane tickets. Meanwhile, touch, community, healthcare and permanent and secure homes are becoming more scarce. What couldn’t be more damning evidence of our screwed-up serotonin pathways than the declining rates of sexual intercourse and the ballooning debts and mortgages?  The society of the spectacle that erodes our power over our own lives is linked to the diffuse sovereignty of corporations, asset holders and real estate moguls. Meanwhile, this turbulent society is coupled with the increased instability of the earth system, leading to a warming world. 

Therefore, only by building a movement armed with a political program that visualizes the totality that binds together the earth system, resource allocation (or stewardship), and the ethical dialectic between humans and the Earth can we begin to reckon with this warming world. Right now, we get caught by loose threads of the unstable system – we grasp in a piece-meal fashion at automobile culture, air travel, the meat industry, or “consumerism” in isolation; this can only generate confusion and solidify the supremacy of the elite. Meanwhile, such a political movement must instead strike into the center of this class structure, the engine that weaves many of the false narratives of climate change. Modern class power has eroded human relationships, replacing play, sexual freedom, and the dissolution of the ego into the Universe itself. Only a life-affirming politics can replace the destructive power of asset holders. 

 

Holocaust Capitalism

Richard Hunsinger argues that migrant concentration camps represent a descent into fascist barbarism and are related to the inherent tendencies of capitalism. 

Photo taken March 27, 2019, Central American migrants wait for food in a holding unit erected by U.S. Customs and Border Protection in El Paso, Texas.

Today the left has come to a common acceptance that the detention centers in which migrants are incarcerated are concentration camps. Despite its truth, this claim has been reduced to a popular point of partisan contention in the spectacle of institutional political theater. While it is important and necessary to expose the routine abuse and murder of those incarcerated in these camps, track ICE raids across the US, and organize legal support to confront these abuses in court, this is not enough. We also need an understanding of how these concentration camps are not merely an aberration of fascism alone but an organic development of late capitalism’s crisis management.

What we are witnessing is not a phenomenon that can be divorced from capital accumulation and the global production process in the imperial epoch. This brutal reality in the last instance is a product of capitalism in its stages of crisis. What we see in the border concentration camps and the privatization model implemented through them is a sustainability measure for capital in its spiraling descent into a new global fascism from which no extant faction of US institutional politics is exempt.

Private incarceration is often framed as a particular abuse within capitalist society so that it may serve as a point of contrast between the two major political parties. Yet from this perspective the crucial role private incarceration plays in the expansion of capital is obscured. A Marxist view of the situation reveals privatization to be an increasingly important mechanism for the appropriation of surplus-value created in production, especially in the past 40 years. It is a further development of the private-property relations fundamental to the capitalist mode of production and the reproduction of capitalist society. In its reproduction, capital overtakes and seizes conventional state functions. Capital here does not eclipse or obliterate the state but merely changes its form. Capital realizes its totalizing logic in the state, exceeds the state, and re-appropriates it as a mechanism for accumulation and concentration. 

It is no surprise to see the familiar villains of this industry at work behind these atrocities. 72% of incarcerated migrants are held in privately-owned camps, the bulk of them owned by CoreCivic (formerly the Corrections Corporation of America) and GEO Group, two of the US’s most enduring and powerful figures of the private-prison industry. The contracts these private entities have with ICE are extremely lucrative, the two companies earned a combined $985 million from them in 2017 alone. Even greater capital investments lie in the many other privately-contracted services necessary to the overall function of the camps, from telephone services to healthcare and everything in between.

The further integration of the concentration camp as a model for capitalism’s sustainability is these prison corporations’ function as sites for the accumulation of finance capital through bank investments, a practice in which many major banking institutions take part. Some have pulled out this year due to public pressure generated from direct action efforts, but they may just as easily creep back into the game. The finance capital that has already been accumulated is now strategically reserved in the form of money-capital as these corporations weather the PR crisis. We can be certain that they are ready for us to stop paying attention.

CoreCivic and GEO Group also heavily involve themselves in political lobbying. The proximity of these corporations to Trump and the GOP often takes center stage in public discourse, but left out are the many contributions they make to Democrats. The Democratic Congressional Campaign Committee received $350,000 in contributions from private-prison industry lobbyists during the 2018 midterm election cycle alone, and there are still instances of individual Democratic candidates accepting gifts and contributions from lobbyists for the industry. What is clear is that capital’s investment in the infrastructure for genocide has bipartisan support and that the false politics represented by the electoral spectacle must not cloud that reality.

America’s failing representative democracy is now infected with a resurgent nationalism that erects itself as a psychological support to the contradiction between capital’s free global movement across borders and the simultaneous restriction of similar movement of labor. Today, the stirrings of a new industrial revolution are already underway and, combined with the looming threat of climate-driven scarcity, are producing a fractured consciousness. People fall back on secure notions of identity and self found in the nation-state.

The political buzzword now adopted by Republicans and Democrats alike is “economic nationalism.” The old rallying cry of “American jobs for American workers” is also a bi-partisan talking point, revealing the reactionary one-party state that has always dominated the US working class. In the case of the concentration camps on the border, then, we should not be fooled by either party’s posturing in addressing the matter. The dual crises of capital and ecology, as well as the descent into fascism, is well out of the hands of any managerial bureaucracy. Behind their blithe opportunism, we must understand that any party will easily maintain the existence of these camps. The nomadic proletariat made real in the Global South’s displacement to the imperial core become a relative surplus population (or industrial reserve army) for the servants of capital, to be absorbed and managed, but not without the creation of an apparatus which can still capture surplus-value. Capitalist society must not waste a chance to further capital’s self-valorization, regardless of its current political commitments.

This holds true for the current upswing in popular support for social democratic reforms in US politics. Social democratic policy prescriptions for capital’s crises and growing racial and class conflict is gaining traction on the right. For example, Tucker Carlson, on his Fox News show, now engages with critiques of free-market capitalism previously foreign to US conservatives, even inviting Angela Nagle, a so-called leftist cultural critic, on as a guest. The manifesto of the El Paso shooter similarly criticizes the failures of American capitalism while supporting social democratic reforms, such as UBI and universal healthcare, to mitigate class conflict while also advocating for an increasingly popular ethnonationalism. In the politics of the nationalist project, to which social democracy unquestionably belongs, the left side of this debate deploys much of the same rhetoric and critiques of “corporatism,” and similarly will not be able to evade the question of border protection and immigration policy that its politics demands of it. Let us not forget that Bernie Sanders too reaffirmed in the last Democratic primary debate his commitment to “stronger border protections.” The project of social democracy, or more generally that of the welfare state, is situated in an imperialist world economy that relies on the exploitation and underdevelopment of the Global South, though it dare not say so out loud.

Furthermore, left projects organizing support on a grassroots level to support these reformist initiatives must remain conscious of the limitations of the nationalist project. Whether there is a claim to reject American nationalism or not, this is the sphere of political action these projects occupy. As Medicare For All gains traction and continues to poll well, dangerous coalitions will form. The migrant as nomadic proletariat here serves a dual function for nationalist politics.

On the one hand, the migrant is that from which the national subject itself must be separate from in order to constitute itself. This separation creates a sense of lack, which is supported by the need it institutes. This psychical manufacture of need supported by a lack finds its material mirror in capitalism’s “original sin” of primitive accumulation, the act of separating laborers from their means of production, initiating the productive consumption of means of subsistence in commodity form. This displacement is the base of capital accumulation and the origin of the proletariat. For capital accumulation to continue, this displacement must continually occur, and it is that which we see functioning in the nomadic proletariat’s creation. But this nomadic proletariat’s existence and movement to the imperial core is contradicted by the core’s reliance on the increasingly fragile social ties of nationality and citizenship wrought by internal displacements for capital accumulation. The nomadic proletariat as migrant becomes a visible sign of these weakening ties, and national identity disintegrates if it absorbs them. The social organization of citizenship must remain separate from the core’s global economic entanglements if displacement as a base of capital accumulation is to continue to function. To that end, it becomes a useful development for the bearers of capital to be able to point to that which is other from the national subject, to then displace the migrant psychically as well as materially, to make them a symbol of that which is lacking in the national subject and use the need thus manufactured to maintain the drive of productive consumption towards accumulation. The political fiction of the nation, therefore, relies on the construction of such lack, and the US national citizen of today is only constituted in so far as it is not the migrant. 

This is where a further need for reform is injected. “American capitalism must be reformed, look at what it is doing to our jobs!” But, as we are not materially separate from a global production process, this return of the need for social democratic reform is then directed towards the consumption of the Global South, its people and its raw material, at the service of the imperial core’s appetite. We are comfortable, then, to see an infrastructure of state support as what we lack, and in turn to see the migrant as the visible manifestation of the state’s failures. This is the implication that the bi-partisan refrain of “economic nationalism” relies upon, for the ability to symbolize lack as such conceals the real process of production that truly directs the phenomena and the relations of which the nationalist project must conceal in order to sustain its fantasy.

This brings us to the other hand of this dual function. Forming amongst the anti-corporate strains of US politics is an understanding of the mutual share of responsibility that Republicans and Democrats possess in their inability to counter the tide of corporate influence, instead taking part in the full transformation of the state into a model of realization for capital. For both the rational actors of the right and the left, the clear reality is that the influence of corporations in politics has utterly compromised all positions on immigration, as many of these large corporations are reliant to some degree on the exploitation of cheaper labor from a nomadic proletariat. This is to an extent correct, but they fail to extend the analysis to encompass capital’s reproduction on a global scale and its role in producing the nomadic proletariat.

Considering the origin of these displacements that have created this nomadic proletariat, we must take into account the long history of US military and political intervention in the affairs of Latin American states which lays a foundation for current waves of migration. Latin American intervention, the intentional and violent arrangements of political power in those countries for the benefit of US interests, is a history with a clear end-goal, and that has been the dominance over the claim to ownership of surplus-value created in production by multinational corporations, that have in turn enforced monocultural agricultural production, super-exploitation, and further alienation of those laborers from that which they produce. 

The agricultural production of Latin American countries is now being affected by climate change as well. This will continue to be a crucial contributing factor to the rise in migration to the United States. The ensuing displacement of these countries’ domestic labor populations is now already exacerbated by the hegemonic relationship, exercised through imperialist foreign and economic policy, between the United States and other such Western liberal democracies over said countries’ production. The result is an increasingly dispossessed and immiserated proletariat in frequently unstable social, political, and economic situations. Such trade agreements as NAFTA and the new USMCA consolidate private ownership of sites of production in Latin American countries, facilitating the capture of surplus-value and further strengthening the property and class relations that global capitalist society relies on for its continual and ever-expanding reproduction.

As capital is mobile on a world scale but labor is not, greater rewards are offered for labor in the core than in the periphery. With the ensuing concentration that the general law of capital accumulation demands, as well as the implementation of dispossession as a means of achieving this accumulation, the core increasingly becomes a site of convergence for the nomadic proletariat, the eye of capital’s global hurricane. But within the core, generations of internal accumulation by dispossession, mostly facilitated by the mechanism of privatization and histories of racialized terror and violence, have fomented unstable conditions and outbursts of revolt. Capital always produces a surplus, and the capital of a global production process in the imperial epoch produces a global relative surplus population. With the situation being as it is in the core, however, what must be done?

The concentration camps here are thus crucial to maintaining the stability of an economic nationalist political program. If “American jobs” are to be maintained for “American workers,” then these relative surplus populations must in turn be utilized so that capitalist society does not forego the opportunity to extract surplus-value from their exploitation. For-profit concentration camps are thus the productive consumption of the relative surplus population produced by capitalist accumulation in the imperial epoch. Privatization as a model of realization for capital here finds its critical place in the scheme of things. The state is merely a series of connective arterial passages for the infrastructure of capital. The concentration camp of today, therefore, is critical infrastructure for valorizing capital by absorbing displaced populations. The incarceration of migrants indefinitely produces absolute surplus-value, as does the indefinite lengthening of the working day.

This can also help to explain the statistics we find currently for ICE removals reported by ICE over the last two recorded fiscal years. In FY 2017 and 2018, total ICE removals numbered 226,119 and 256,085, respectively. These are not insignificant declines from much of the Obama era’s numbers, with ICE removals for FY 2013 and 2014 reaching such heights as 368,644 and 315,943, respectively. FY 2015 and 2016 saw relative declines to 235,413 and 240,255, respectively, as a result of minor reformist initiatives undertaken at the time. This period too, however, saw a solidifying hold on privatization for ICE detention. The Trump administration’s numbers retain the average closely, and it may very well be a result of the minimum necessary population levels that these privatized models of ICE concentration camps require for their functioning and stable capture of surplus-value in their incarceration. Some analyses often discuss these declines as a result of an overloaded immigration court system unduly burdened by the escalation of ICE raids of increasingly dubious legality. It is rather more likely that indefinite detention and procedural dysfunction are vital to the continual production of absolute surplus-value and give it the elasticity that it requires.

To see how profitable indefinite incarceration in the concentration camp model is, we can look at the cost per night of maintaining detainees. According to ICE’s FY 2018 budget, the average cost of a single bed is $133.99 a day, though this figure is disputed. For mothers and children together in so-called family residential centers, it is $319.00 a day. For the beds in the tent city camps made to hold children separated from their families, they are $775.00 a day. These costs are supported by federal contracts with the corporations that own these camps, and costs are re-evaluated per annum with the potential of increasing federal funding if deemed necessary and in turn supported by Congress’ allocation and at the same time being continually bolstered by private investments made from other corporations seeking to in turn valorize their capital through consumption of products in the concentration camp. The whole apparatus is one designed for the ruthless exploitation through dispossession of the migrant’s agency and movement. It is no surprise then that, as capital seeks its expanded reproduction within this model of realization, ICE’s body count climbs and climbs. 

Any illusions as to the capacity possessed by the US state or capitalist society at large to address this current monstrosity must be extinguished. So long as migration intensifies on a global scale and the more developed core countries retain their trajectory of hyper-development by means of capital accumulated through the Global South’s continual exploitation and dispossession, the migrant concentration camp will be a stabilizing mechanism for the crisis of capital. The state machine, in pursuit of the stability of the nationalist project, seeks out structures to adapt our desires to the needs of capital and its drive towards accumulation, seen in the affirmation of the importance of the “American” worker. Even as left projects seek to better the lives of the US proletariat through social democratic reform, they are acting in the interior of the state machine in lock-step motion with the rise of fascist ideology. The incompatibility of this politics with a goal of universal emancipation that includes the abolition of the incarceration of the nomadic proletariat, therefore, necessitates a rupture with this procedural left so that we may combat the suicidal ideation of fascism. The project of border abolition is bound up with the self-abolition and emancipation of the proletariat, and affirming the importance of a national proletariat over the nomadic only sustains the lifeblood of capital. 

History shows us that the only sufficient course of action to be taken then must be the liberation of these camps and the dismantling of their supportive infrastructures, and strategies to this end are still taking shape. In the fearless example laid for us by Willem Van Spronsen, we saw transportation vehicles of the Tacoma Northwest Detention Center taken out of commission. We must seek to continue to reproduce such models of direct action on a more expansive, mass scale, with the further coordination of such with the efforts of the incarcerated. Protests and direct actions organized on banks investing in the concentration camps have made said banks pull out of their contracts with them. Direct actions on massive corporations like Amazon and other tech companies are aiming to disrupt the critical data infrastructures that are being invested into and developed in the concentration camps, and this is a crucial space of engagement. We must continue to build the capacity, scale, and mass support for these actions that will become necessary if we do indeed succeed in impeding the concentration camps function as a model of realization for capital value.

This is where we find the kinetic movement of fascism forming, its material basis for potential genocide in capitalism’s organic adoption of the concentration camp as a model of realization. We may hear the right’s racialized rhetoric on immigration and criminality as a rejection and demonization of the migrant. Rather, this rhetoric is that which wills the caravan into existence, both as a result of and a driving force of capital accumulation. As a result, this relative surplus population is made into a model of capital’s realization by means of its bodily dispossession and a psychological support for nationalism. The transition to fascism is seamless, because the progression is inherent in capital’s crisis in the US where the capitalist mode of production is so highly-developed with heavily ingrained institutions of White Supremacy. Capital’s tornado reaches an intensity in magnitude of crisis to make the qualitative shift to the black hole of fascism’s suicidal state. The movement is not yet complete, and we may yet have time to prevent a new American holocaust. Its death will only be real if we act.